For Conscience Sake Analysis Essay

Abstract

The debate on the meaning of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (RFRA) is rapidly developing. Taking three snapshots in the bill's history (in 1993 at its origin, in 2014 during Burwell v. Hobby Lobby, and in 2015 after Obergefell v. Hodges), this essay evaluates the stances taken on the RFRA by the American Civil Liberties Union (ACLU) and the US Conference of Catholic Bishops (USCCB). Although the ACLU initially supported the bill, it now campaigns against it. In contrast the USCCB, once hesitant to endorse the RFRA, fervently defends it today. Evaluating these pivoting positions, this essay suggests that at the heart of the debate on RFRA lies a difference in understanding the right to follow one's conscience in the public square.

Lay Summary: This essay evaluates how the ACLU and the USCCB differ in their understanding of conscience. Next, the essay demonstrates that this difference leads to opposing viewpoints on the Religious Freedom Restoration Act today. Although both initially supported the Religious Freedom Restoration Act at its signing in 1993, the ACLU has now disavowed the bill after it had been used to permit following religious-based conscience in the public square.

Keywords: Conscience, Religious Freedom Restoration Act, ACLU, Burwell v. Hobby Lobby, USCCB, Obergefell v. Hodges, Secularism

Introduction

Since being passed in 1993, the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (RFRA) has played a critical role in determining the boundaries of conscience in the public square. The RFRA is designed to give a person of faith the procedure to assert that the federal government has burdened his or her religious beliefs. The RFRA was signed into law with broad public support, and although the law has not changed, moral standards have pluralized since it was enacted. In response, religious persons have become increasingly aggressive in using the RFRA to protect their religious exercise. This essay focuses on three events in the RFRA's timeline—its origin, its role in Burwell v. Hobby Lobby (the Supreme Court ruling on mandated insurance coverage for contraception), and its possible applications after Obergefell v. Hodges (the Supreme Court ruling on the right to same-sex marriage). These three events will be considered from the positions taken by the US Conference of Catholic Bishops (USCCB) and the American Civil Liberties Union (ACLU). Using these two organizations, it will be clear that the heart of the RFRA debate is the prerogative to externalize one's conscience in a pluralistic society.

A Brief History of the Debate over the RFRA

A brief history will assist in understanding the current debate. The foundation of the RFRA begins with the First Amendment, specifically the Free Exercise Clause, italicized here: “Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof.” The breadth of this constitutional liberty has been defined by several Supreme Court interpretations, notably Sherbert v. Verner (1963) and Wisconsin v. Yoder (1972). In these two cases, a test known as “strict scrutiny” was applied to determine whether or not the government had violated a right to religious liberty. Strict scrutiny required the government to prove that if any action were to compromise religious beliefs or duties, it must be of compelling public interest and applied by the least-restrictive, most-accommodating means. Thus, under strict scrutiny, religious liberty was prioritized but not unlimited (Morgan 2014, 176–77). Religious liberty enjoyed this protection until 1990, when Employment Division v. Smith (494 U.S. [1990]) was brought to the Supreme Court. In this case, two members of the Native American Church were denied state unemployment benefits after testing positive for peyote, an illegal drug used during their religious ritual. In a 6–3 decision supporting the state, the Court ruled that the Free Exercise Clause does not exempt the “free exercise of religion from a neutral law of general applicability” (Morgan 2014, 177). Thus, strict scrutiny no longer applied to neutral laws, removing a critical protection of religious exercise.

The ruling set off a firestorm of controversy, leading to the introduction of the RFRA. In contrast to the Court's ruling in Smith, the RFRA proposed that government could “not substantially burden a person's exercise of religion,” even if the burden results from a general rule (Religious Freedom Restoration Act 1993). The public consensus, recognizing that personal religious convictions should be among the highest protected civil liberties, ensured support for the bill from both parties and diverse faith traditions, including the United States Catholic Conference (USCC), which later merged with the National Conference of Catholic Bishops to form the USCCB (Gaffney 1994, 6). The bill passed by unanimous voice-vote in the House, passed 97-3 in the Senate, and was penned into law by President Bill Clinton in 1993.

The American Civil Liberties Union unequivocally supported the bill. At a congressional hearing, the ACLU president, Nadine Strossen, called it, “a great privilege to be here testifying on behalf of this critically important statute.” She went on to say:

I think it is all in the name: the Religious Freedom Restoration Act. That is an accurate description of what this legislation would do, no more and no less … The ACLU strongly supports [the RFRA] because it restores religious liberty to its rightful place as a preferred value and a fundamental right within the American constitutional system. The First Amendment's guarantee of the “free exercise of religion” has proven to be the boldest and most successful experiment in religious freedom the world has known. (US House 1993, 63)

The USCC took a more cautious view. General Consul Mark Chopko, in the same hearing, spoke on behalf of the USCC:

[The bishops] are concerned about the frightening government power with too great a handle to interfere into religious activities … They do believe that the government may not impair religious practices without compelling justification, and therefore they join the search for a solution to the Smith case. (US House 1993, 48)

While the USCC agreed with the need to protect religious freedom, they were initially uncertain whether the RFRA was the appropriate answer. At the hearing, Mr. Chopko went on to say, “religious freedom and how best to protect it are complex issues that do not lend themselves readily to simple solutions. A major problem is that [the RFRA] seems to adopt a single test to be applied to a multitude of situations” (US House 1993, 37). As we will soon see, the USCC had a more expansive understanding of religious liberty, and considered the RFRA too naive to address its nature. However, within a year, the USCC conferred their support to the RFRA, which played a significant role in the lopsided vote to pass the measure.

Thus, in 1993, both the ACLU and USCC supported the RFRA. With such unusual allies, one legal scholar commented, “the RFRA was warmly received and intensely celebrated by a remarkably diverse group of supporters—from secular liberals in the ACLU to religious conservatives” (Idleman 1994, 248–49). Neither constituency anticipated how the RFRA would evolve in practice. While many rallied to support the sentence that “government shall not substantially burden a person's exercise of religion even if the burden results from a rule of general applicability” (Religious Freedom Restoration Act 1993), the phrase “exercise of religion” was vaguely defined under the First Amendment. Therefore, both the ACLU and the USCC understood the RFRA according to their own definition of religious exercise.

Liberty From and Liberty To

To understand how the RFRA would later be interpreted, let us consider the exercise of religion as it relates to the exercise of conscience. Bishop De Smedt, of Belgium, explains it this way:

What, therefore, is meant by “religious freedom”? Positively, religious freedom is the right of the human person to the free exercise of religion according to the dictates of his conscience. Negatively, it is immunity from all external force in his personal relations with God. (quoted in Lori 2015).

Religious freedom can be understood as a spectrum containing internal and external liberties. On one end of the spectrum lies negative liberty, liberty from government interference in religious expression (i.e., to gather to profess a creed, to have a sacred ceremony and rites, to elect ministers of the faith without government encroachment, etc.) This is an internal expression, exercised within the home or a religious community. On the other end of the spectrum lies positive liberty, the liberty to live one's conscience throughout the day (i.e., to invoke God's blessings in a public speech, to collect canned goods for refugees at one's workplace, to refrain from participating in an elective abortion, etc.). An external expression, such liberties are exercised outside the home or religious community, such as in hospitals or schools.

For the USCCB, the full exercise of conscience requires both internal and external expression. This is laid out in Dignitatis humanae, the first magisterial document on religious liberty, which provided the ground rules for the Church to relate to secular states. Written in 1965 during the Second Vatican Council, the Declaration on Religious Freedom Dignitatis humanae is designed to bring the Church into closer contact with a global culture:

This Vatican Council declares that the human person has a right to religious freedom. This freedom means that all men are to be immune from coercion on the part of individuals or of social groups and of any human power, in such wise that no one is to be forced to act in a manner contrary to his own beliefs, whether privately or publicly, whether alone or in association with others, within due limits. (Vatican Council II 1965, n. 2)

Guided by Dignitatis humanae, the USCCB supports the freedom from governmental interference. For the USCCB, however, this is a minimum. Archbishop William Lori, chair of the USCCB's Ad Hoc Committee on Religious Liberty, would call this liberty-from a necessary building block, but nonetheless incomplete (Lori 2015). For Dignitatis humane goes on to state:

The council further declares that the right to religious freedom has its foundation in the very dignity of the human person as this dignity is known through the revealed word of God and by reason itself … On his part, man perceives and acknowledges the imperatives of the divine law through the mediation of conscience. In all his activity, a man is bound to follow his conscience in order that he may come to God, the end and purpose of life. It follows that he is not to be forced to act in a manner contrary to his conscience. Nor, on the other hand, is he to be restrained from acting in accordance with his conscience, especially in matters religious … Injury therefore is done to the human person and to the very order established by God for human life, if the free exercise of religion is denied in society, provided just public order is observed. (Vatican Council II 1965, n. 2)

The RFRA at least grants the negative liberty to conscience, protecting the freedom from coercion by government. The ACLU and USCCB rallied behind this interpretation. However, for the ACLU, protecting the internal expression of conscience is sufficient. Thus, from 1993 to 2014, the ACLU considered the RFRA to be a comprehensive protection of conscience, whereas the USCCB would consider it partial in that the law only protected the internal life of the Church, but did not protect the person of faith in a pluralistic or secular public square.

Shifting around the RFRA with Burwell v. Hobby Lobby

The political alignment of the ACLU and the USCCB around the RFRA shifted with the 2014 landmark Supreme Court decision, Burwell v. Hobby Lobby (573 U.S. [2014]). The Supreme Court had been asked to rule whether closely held businesses (i.e., private, for-profit businesses that are owned by persons of faith) are considered persons under the law, and may likewise seek protection under the RFRA from a federal mandate to include contraception in their employees’ health insurance policies. The owners of Hobby Lobby conscientiously objected specifically to the mechanism of action of FDA-approved intrauterine devices (Jost 2013, 4). The question at hand was whether the owners of Hobby Lobby have the liberty to externalize their conscience in the workplace, even if to do so limited access to contraception for their employees. Given that the petitioners were seeking to use the RFRA to protect a positive expression of conscience, the ACLU swapped sides on the bill.

Instead of debating the legal application of the RFRA, the ALCU proposed that the externalization of conscience is dangerous if it undermines another's sexual liberty. “We submit this brief to highlight an important lesson of history: as our society has moved towards greater equality for racial minorities and women, it has been less willing to accept religion as a justification for discrimination” (ACLU et al. 2014, 6). Their argument is as follows: like most Americans, but unlike the owners of Hobby Lobby, the ACLU does not morally object to contraception. It considers contraception “a tool, like education, essential to women's equality” (ACLU et al. 2014, 9). Therefore, denying full access to contraception (for any reason) is likened to denying full women's equality. Thus, the employer's conscientious objection of contraceptives they consider to be abortifacients is considered discriminatory to the female employees. The ACLU bluntly states that conscience must be restrained to one's private life only: “Although the business owners are certainly entitled to their religious beliefs, the companies are not permitted to invoke those beliefs to discriminate against their female employees” (ACLU et al. 2014, 33). The ACLU acknowledges the validity of the employer's conscientious objection, but the moment their conscience spills into the public square, it becomes unlicensed and even discriminatory. Thus, when applying a neutral law—the Department of Health and Human Services (HHS) mandate, in this case—a conscientious objection should be internalized. No accommodation should be made for the external expression of their conscience.

The amicus brief of the USCCB posits a broader understanding of conscience to support the owners of Hobby Lobby. The brief reflected the complementary understanding of conscience (liberty-from and liberty-to) discussed in Dignitatis humanae. In addressing the suggestion that internal conscience should be separated from its external pursuit, the USCCB states:

Religion is not something that can or should be divorced from the commercial sphere. Indeed, it is religion that often serves to direct that sphere toward the common good … Moreover, the notion that religious believers or the companies they own cannot or do not exercise religion rests on an unduly cramped definition of religious liberty and runs contrary to the manner in which Christians have understood their faith for centuries. Religion is not confined to the four walls of a church or to the private life of a believer. (USCCB 2014, 7)

Although the general public may consider the HHS mandate neutral and even insignificant, for a business owner who holds tenable that life begins at conception, it is undue and unconscionable. Thus, without an accommodation, the business owners are posed with the mutually exclusive solutions of violating their beliefs or complying with the mandate to provide contraception.

In a 5–4 ruling, the Supreme Court ruled that employers possessed conscience prerogatives, and the federal government did not offer a compelling interest and least-restrictive means in which to violate them as required by the RFRA. Therefore the conscientious objections of the employers must be accommodated. Although the court majority opinion made clear that the scope of the analysis is directed solely to the contraception mandate, it was a ruling that provided a means for religious liberty to become more prominent in the marketplace, supporting an external exercise of conscience long sought-after and regarded by religious communities as necessary.

Unsettled by the RFRA's exemption of an employer's conscience, the ACLU formally disavowed the bill in an op-ed in the Washington Post titled, “Why we can no longer support the religious freedom law.” In the article, the ACLU's deputy legal director stated:

[The ACLU] can no longer support [the RFRA] in its current form. For more than 15 years, we have been concerned how the RFRA could be used to discriminate against others … while the RFRA may serve as a shield, it is now often used as a sword to discriminate against women, gay and transgender people … Yes, religious freedom needs protection. But religious liberty doesn't mean the right to discriminate or impose one's views on others. (Melling 2015)

The harsh language criticizing the RFRA is a stark departure from their support at the bill's hearing 23 years prior. What changed? Not the RFRA. The current form of the bill as it applies to federal laws was not amended. Instead, the RFRA is being applied and interpreted in a shifting cultural context (Norris and Inglehardt 2007, 31–32). The ACLU decision to wash their hands clean of the bill represents an interpretation that the Free Exercise Clause protects a person's conscience only in private matters, where it can safely be exercised without potential friction. In this view, the external expression of one's conscience is hastily mistranslated as paternalistic. Its exercise outside the religious community, should it affect another individual's autonomous expression, is cheaply equivalent to the proselytizing of one's theocratic pretensions. In this secularized worldview, churches, synagogues, and mosques are able to grow and shrink with the ebb and flow of the population that fills them, but not contribute to the public conscience. Outside the religious institution, the public sphere should be sterilized of any religious expression.

The ACLU would argue that the internal expression of conscience is the only appropriate method to achieve tolerance in a pluralistic society. It would suggest that religious tolerance, like internal conscience, gives the opportunity to pray the Rosary, recite the Shema Yisrael, or face the Kaaba without interference. However, as one enters and exits the public sphere, for the sake of the common good, religious conscience must checked in and out like a salesclerk clocking his or her hours. However, many religious leaders contend that this a false notion of religious liberty built on a narrow understanding of the common good. Returning to our spectrum of liberty-to and liberty-from discussed above, we can better understand the relationship of religious tolerance to religious liberty. Religious tolerance is the freedom from government coercion, and a building block to express the freedom to exercise religious liberty. While religious tolerance and religious liberty are connected, they are not equivalent for the same reason that one's internal and external expressions are related, but not interchangeable. In a letter, the Union of Orthodox Jewish Congregations of America draws this distinction, “a religious entity is not insular, but engaged with broader society … Many faiths firmly believe in being open to and engaged with broader society and fellow citizens of other faiths” (Diament 2012). Pope Francis shares this sentiment too, saying in his first encyclical Evangelii gaudium, “religion [cannot be] relegated to the inner sanctum of personal life, without influence on societal and national life” (Francis 2013, n. 183). Consequently, the drive to internalize conscience has deleterious effects on the practice of religion. In a lecture to seminarians, Archbishop William Lori discusses this challenge:

Clearly our institutions of education and service have entered a more challenging environment for bearing witness to Christ and his teaching. This environment has deteriorated due to factors within the Church, including: lessened church attendance, scandals and divisions within the Church, and diminished knowledge and acceptance of church teachings, especially moral teachings. But that environment has also been made difficult by factors external to the Church, including: the societal loss of consensus on moral values, the view that religion as a cultural force is spent, and laws, rules, and court decisions that reflect those changed attitudes. (emphasis added; Lori 2014)

Religious leaders are growing dependent on the RFRA to claim that their conscience is being trampled upon by a religiously unconscionable federal stature. The ACLU, in contrast, now considers the RFRA as a necessary abandonment in order to preserve what they consider to be a completely tolerant society.

Positions Entrenched

If Burwell v. Hobby Lobby pitted the ACLU against the USCCB on opposite sides of the RFRA, their positions have calcified after Obergefell v. Hodges (576 US [2015]). In this case, a 5-4 Supreme Court ruled that, under the Due Process Clause and Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, the fundamental right to marry is guaranteed to same-sex couples. This requires all states and territories in the United States to issue marriage licenses to same-sex couples. The RFRA was not used explicitly during the proceedings, but the undertones of religious freedom were present throughout the case (USCCB 2015). With the liberty to same-sex marriage imminently protected under the Fourteenth Amendment, and the right to religious liberty protected under the First, a tangle of liberties results (Green 2015). In his dissenting opinion, Supreme Court Justice Clarence Thomas elaborates on the inevitability of this conflict:

The Court's decision [that same-sex marriage is a fundamental right] will have unavoidable and wide-ranging implications for religious liberty. In our society, marriage is not simply a governmental institution; it is a religious institution as well. Today's decision might change the former, but it cannot change the latter. It appears all but inevitable that the two will come into conflict, particularly as individuals and churches are confronted with demands to participate and endorse civil marriages between same-sex couples. (Obergefell v. Hodges 2015, 15)

Justice Thomas claims that the court's majority opinion grossly misunderstands religious liberty, which has damaging consequences for conscience. He points out that without a legislative accommodation, the ruling effectively limits the exercise of one's religious-based conscience:

[The majority opinion of the court] makes only a weak gesture toward religious liberty in a single paragraph. And even that gesture indicates a misunderstanding of religious liberty in our nation's tradition. Religious liberty is about more than just the protection for “religious organizations and persons as they seek to teach the principles that are so fulfilling and so central to their lives and faiths” [as claimed in the majority's opinion]. Religious liberty is about freedom of action in matters of religion generally, and the scope of that liberty is directly correlated to the civil restrains placed upon religious practice … [violating this] has potentially ruinous consequences for religious liberty. (Obergefell v. Hodges 2015, 16)

Obergefell v. Hodges was decided on June 26, 2015. The ACLU ran its op-ed abandoning the RFRA on June 25. This is hardly a coincidence. In anticipation of the Supreme Court's ruling that same-sex marriage is a fundamental right, religious-based conscience was soon to be on the wrong-side of the law, with a Pandora's box of discrimination claims about to be opened. Will religious adoption agencies be required to violate their beliefs and place children in same-sex households, or will same-sex couples sue the adoption agencies on grounds that they were discriminated against? Will religious colleges lose access to federal funding because of their policies on same-sex marriage, or will same-sex couples sue a religious college for not being granted housing designated for married couples? Without an accommodation, claims to religious freedom and claims of discrimination are negatively correlated. As one legal journalist put it, “the Supreme Court's ruling in favor of same-sex marriage … has set up the country for two new waves of discrimination claims: those made by same-sex couples and those made by religious Americans who oppose same-sex marriage” (Green 2015). A post-Obergefell legal landscape is ambiguous, and at this point still largely speculative. However, energized after Obergefell and on a mission to eliminate any hint of inequity, the ACLU began to swiftly and fiercely lobby against the RFRA legislation, considering it a bastion of externalized religious conscience. This position completed its 180° pivot around the legislation: from supporting the RFRA at its birth, to opposing it during the Hobby Lobby proceedings, the ACLU is now prepared to see its demise. The vector charted by the USCCB has taken quite the opposite course: from cautiously approving the RFRA at its origin, to fervently defending it today.

The Essence of the RFRA

More than two decades after the RFRA was signed into law, both the ACLU and the USCCB would admit that the bill is not perfectly applied in every case. The RFRA finds itself at the heart of the battle of understanding the substance of the First Amendment. The German philosopher Jürgen Habermas considers this to be a uniquely American challenge:

The secularization of state powers [in America] did not serve primarily the negative purpose of protecting citizens against the compulsion to adopt a faith against their own will. It was instead designed to guarantee the settlers who had turned their backs on Old Europe the positive liberty to continue to exercise their respective religion without hindrance. For this reason, in the present American debate on the political role of religion, all sides have been able to claim their loyalty to the constitution. (Habermas 2006, 3)

Conflicts over deeply held beliefs and public policy will remain a characteristic of democracy.

By entering into the conversation of conscience, the RFRA was bound to lose its early support as the law was applied. Recognizing religious liberty means standing up for unpopular religious expression within constitutionally appropriate bounds. This is the fabric of true coexistence and pluralism. To the secularist, the bill potentially invites a cacophony of accommodations for “odd” religious expressions: a Muslim woman will refrain from serving alcohol on an airplane, a Catholic nurse will avoid an elective termination, a Jewish man will don out-of-uniform sidelocks in military attire. These are the inevitable challenges of a pluralistic society. These challenges, however, do not discredit the RFRA. Rather, they affirm its integrity. Religious conscience in its various expressions contributes to the common good and to constructive public discourse. The ACLU position on the RFRA today, to throw out the baby with the bathwater, would put religious-based conscience at serious risk. Without adequate protection, a pluralistic society will lose the voices that contribute to its plurality. The words of President Bill Clinton, at the RFRA's signing, continue to ring true:

We are a people of faith. We have been so secure in that faith that we have enshrined in our Constitution protection for people who profess no faith. And good for us for doing so. That is what the first amendment is all about. But let us never believe that the freedom of religion imposes on any of us some responsibility to run from our convictions. Let us instead respect one another's faiths, fight to the death to preserve the rights of every American to practice whatever convictions he or she has, but bring our values back to the table of American discourse to heal our troubled land. (Clinton 1993, 2000–2001)

Modeled after the federal version signed in 1993, state legislatures have brought similar bills to vote. However, as seen in Indiana and Mississippi, the individual bills are met with strong criticism from business and entertainment leaders. The state bills are cast as discriminatory exclusively in the context of same-sex marriage, although the text does not specifically address the issue and remains virtually identical to that signed into law by President Clinton. If the national conversation continues to consider conscience and discrimination as grossly synonymous, the RFRA is not likely to survive. This puts the sincerely held intellectual and moral traditions of religious communities—and the fabric of plurality—at risk. The RFRA is worthy of our defense, because strict scrutiny promotes a consistent, reality driven analysis of conscience in the public square. It is not a trump card, and does not guarantee one's conscientious expression. However, it provides the means for legal evaluation of beliefs as applied in America today. The Catholic response, therefore, should be firm yet careful. First, as members of a pluralistic society, we must work to defend the conscientious expression of other religions, within constitutional and morally appropriate bounds. Second, using the democratic process, we must emphatically support political leaders that understand the timeless importance of the First Amendment. Finally, conscience is best understood as a well-developed capacity for moral judgment, therefore we must continually seek to develop it internally. Our conscience should be neither a shield nor a sword, but an opportunity to share the freshness and fragrance of the Gospels.

Acknowledgements

This research was conducted under the mentorship of Steven Miles, M.D., at the Center for Bioethics at the University of Minnesota. Research support was provided by Michael P. Kurmlavage, a law student at Rutgers School of Law. I would like to thank my aunt and uncle, Maryann and Joseph, who generously hosted me in Minneapolis. Additionally, I would like to thank Dr. Miles for his unassuming example of open-mindedness in academic medicine and research.

Biographical Note

Luke Gatta and his wife, Brittany, are interns, in obstetrics and gynecology and internal medicine respectively, at Duke University Medical Center.

References

  • ACLU. et al. 2014 Brief for Burwell v. Hobby Lobby as Amici Curiae supporting petitioners, 573 U.S.
  • Clinton William. 1993. Remarks on singing the Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993. Federal Register of Public Papers 2 (November 16): 2000–01.
  • Diament Nathan. 2012. Union of Orthodox Jewish Congregations critiques administration denial of expanded exemption for religious entities’ liberties in health insurance plans; Calls on Congress to redress through legislation. Orthodox Union Advocacy Center. January 24, 2012. http://advocacy.ou.org/union-of-orthodox-jewish-congregations-critiques-administration-denial-of-expanded-exemption-for-religious-entities-liberties-in-health-insurance-plans-calls-on-congress-to-redress-through-legislat/.
  • Employment Division 1990. Department of Human Resources of Oregon v. Smith, 494 U.S.
  • Francis Pope. 2013. Evangelii gaudium. http://w2.vatican.va/content/francesco/en/apost_exhortations/documents/papa-francesco_esortazione-ap_20131124_evangelii-gaudium.html.
  • Gaffney Edward. 1994. Pass the peyote: The Religious Freedom Restoration Act. Commonwealth21, no. 2: 5–6.
  • Green E. 2015. Gay rights may come at the cost of religious freedom. The Atlantic. July 15. http://www.theatlantic.com/politics/archive/2015/07/legal-rights-lgbt-discrimination-religious-freedom-claims/399278/.
  • Habermas Jurgen. 2006. Religion in the public sphere. European Journal of Philosophy14, no. 1: 1–25. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0378.2006.00241.x [Cross Ref]
  • Idleman Scott C. 1994. The religious freedom restoration act: Pushing the limits of legislative power. Texas Law Review73, no. 2f: 247–334.
  • Jost T. S. 2013. Religious freedom and women's health—the litigation on contraception. New England Journal of Medicine368, no. 1: 4–6. doi: 10.1056/NEJMp1214605 [PubMed][Cross Ref]
  • Lori William. 2014. The freedom to bear witness. Lecture presented at the Workshop on Religious Freedom, Mount St. Mary's Seminary, Emmitsburg, MD, November 15.
  • Lori William. 2015. Continuing the search for religious liberty: The contribution of Dignitatis Humanae. Lecture presented at the lecture series Fifty Years after Vatican II's Dignitatis Humanae, April 21. St. Charles Borromeo Seminary, Overbrook, PA, April 21.
  • Melling Louise. 2015. ACLU: Why we can no longer support ‘religious freedom’ law. Washington Post. June 25. http://wapo.st/1e6WIWI.
  • Morgan James F. 2014. Crafting enhanced rights for the religious business owner: An examination of the Supreme Court decision in Hobby Lobby. Labor Law Journal65, no. 4: 175–88.
  • Norris Pippa, and Inglehardt Ronald. 2007. Uneven secularization in the United States and Western Europe. In Democracy and the new religious pluralism, ed. Banchoff T., editor. , 31–57. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Obergefell v. Hodges2015 James Obergefell et al. v. Richard Hodges, Ohio Department of Health et al., 576 U.S.
  • Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993, 42 U.S.C. § 2000bb.
  • Sylvia Burwell v. Hobby Lobby 2014. 573 U.S.
  • U.S. House 1993. Subcommittee on Civil and Constitutional Rights of the House Committee on the Judiciary. Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1991 Hearing. Government Printing Office: 33–86.
  • USCCB 2014. Brief for Burwell v. Hobby Lobby as Amici Curiae supporting defendants, 573 U.S.
  • USCCB 2015 Brief for Obergefell v. Hodges as Amici Curiae supporting respondents, 576 U.S.
  • Vatican Council II 1965. Declaration on Religious Freedom Dignitatis humanae.

Articles from The Linacre Quarterly are provided here courtesy of SAGE Publications

Martin Heidegger was one of the most radical thinkers of the 20th century regarding phenomenological and existential philosophy. His writings influenced the philosophical world and continental Europe in particular, whilst gaining many German and French followers. His university professor, Edmund Husserl, who was arguably the pioneer for phenomenology, greatly influenced Heidegger. This is because it was Heidegger who, so to speak “carried the torch” for phenomenology and expanded the field into new grounds.

However, Heidegger changed the direction and motive for his phenomenological method in comparison to Husserl. Because Husserl had a scientific background to his studies, his method for phenomenology leaned more so towards scientific understanding rather than a philosophical one. Heidegger however did not look to revert his findings back to the scientific field of knowledge but rather philosophy, and specifically philosophy of fundamental questions, which in the book we will examine today. The Book is Being and Time, Heidegger’s most well known publication, a ground breaking philosophical text that deals with the fundamental philosophy of man, authenticity, Dasein and most importantly, asking the question ‘what is the meaning of Being?’. Such a radicalisation occurred in Being and Time specifically regarding how one views the situated-ness of being in regards to Being-in-the-world. And yet all of this accomplished whilst Being and Time was deemed an unfinished project.

This essay will focus on a particular section of Being and Time[1] in which Heidegger made an account for conscience and perhaps most importantly, creates the notion for ‘the call of conscience’. Whilst explaining and analysing Heidegger’s notion of the ‘conscience’, I will investigate the philosophy of responsiveness and examine to what extent it is compatible with Heidegger’s conscience and in particular the ‘call of conscience’. The essay will further look into how exactly Heideggerian ‘conscience’ cannot be explained through responsiveness and why it is the case.

Before the comparative analysis begins, the particular section in which Heidegger covers conscience needs to be explored in order to understand why it could potentially be compatible with responsiveness. Although this summary will bypass details of the process of Dasein becoming authentic, I intend for it to demonstrate enough to make an understanding. The chapter begins with Heidegger describing the environment and process in which authenticity can occur.    Because inauthenticity is our common, socially normative state, according to Heidegger “Authentic Being-one’s-Self takes the definite form of an existentiell modification of the “they””, meaning that in becoming authentic beings, an existentiell modification needs to occur.

However it is not that simple, because, “The “they” has always kept Dasein from taking hold of these possibilities of Being.” And the “they” keep the individual within social norms, making this a vicious cycle. However, “This process can be reversed only if Dasein specifically brings itself back to itself from its lostness in the “they””, when this happens, an existentiell modification occurs. Heidegger goes on to explain how exactly this ‘authentifi-cation’ occurs, “This must be accomplished by making up for not choosing [Nachholen einer Wahl]. But “making up” for not choosing signifies choosing to make this choice– deciding for a potentiality-for-Being, and making this decision from one’s own Self.” This potentiality, according to Heidegger, is synonymous to the “voice of conscience”.

This is in a sense a ‘meeting point’ for Heidegger in regards to Dasein’s conscience and authentic Being. Because for Heidegger, authenticity is where we find singularity in ourselves, a paramount ambition for Heidegger in Being and Time. So if we see that it is conscience that calls its own Being into potentiality for authenticity, which becomes manifested as its most fundamental characteristic, care. As Heidegger reiterates, “The call of conscience-that is, conscience itself-has its ontological possibility in the fact that Dasein, in the very basis of its Being, is care.” This is because care is the manifestation of Dasein’s “that-it-is”, making care the mode-of-authentic-being for Dasein. From representing Heidegger’s arguments as they were, we can see that conscience itself is a caller, or rather, the caller which calls itself (conscience) to itself (Dasein) in order to find authenticity within him or herself.

This leads us to ask, what exactly is the ‘call’ in the ‘call of conscience’? In a sense, it is the revealing of Dasein’s authentic Being by an event of myself making a call to myself. But it is noteworthy that the call itself “is a silent call that silences the chatter of the world and brings me back to myself”.[2] The call silences the “they” and although the call itself has no real substance it calls us to authenticity, which in essence, is taking responsibility for the project that is Dasein.

As Gordon states in an analysis of Heidegger, “The essence of Dasein lies in its “to-be”…What is more, Dasein’s mode of being lies in its being toward possibilities in such a way that its own being in such a way that its own being and choice of possibilities are an issue for it.”[3] The previous quote demonstrates what exactly the “call of conscience” reveals for us, that Dasein itself is a project as opposed to a concrete unchanging essence and part of this project is, as Heidegger puts it, “[Dasein is] that entity which in its Being has this very Being as an issue”.

Because Being is an issue, we have an existential responsibility to engage in the project that is Dasein. This is the meeting point for the essay in regards to Heidegger’s analysis of the “call of conscience” and responsiveness, because in answering “the call”, an act of response occurs, but to what extent will be further examined later in the essay. In order to compare the two ideas, it is important to introduce the philosophy of responsiveness and its implications.

Responsiveness, in essence, is ‘the’ mode-of-being in regards to our fundamental nature, which is that of being a responsive being. Responsiveness is not a concrete entity but rather a way (perhaps ‘the way’) of being. However it must be noted that it is different to a reaction, because a response is of a reciprocal nature that involves a two-way event and a presupposition as opposed to a reaction. Responsiveness is a vital quality in taking responsibility because responding places us in a position to be responsible. In summary, responsiveness demonstrates the importance and fundamental nature that responding gives to human beings, thus it is labelled as an existential anthropology.

The issue that this essay will attempt to deal with is whether Heidegger’s “call of conscience” is compatible with responsiveness and in particular, whether the “call of conscience” can be explained through responsiveness. If we look back to the call itself and examine the properties and characteristics of it, we should have an understanding. Is the call an act that presupposes before and after the act, that there is something else outside of the response itself? I would suggest that there is a pre-suppositional act in the call itself because the conscience has at the very least a sub-conscious understanding of intending to bring us to authenticity, meaning that there is an awareness of what is outside these things. The use of the word conscience commonly regards intuitive moral thinking, but for Heidegger the moral element is not dealt with and I see his use of conscience as a faculty of intuitive thinking that in a sense awakens us. Although it may appear that way, I do not intend to diverge into Freudian style divisions of the mind but rather keeping our conscience with our inauthentic being unified.

In determining whether Heidegger’s conscience can be explained through responsiveness, it is important to examine if the answering to the call is an act of responsiveness. Because if the answer to the call can be explained through responsiveness, then the “call of conscience” can be explained completely through responsiveness. For clarifications sake, it should be noted that answering the call is taking responsibility for ones existential project, which is Dasein.

In answering the call, an understanding must be involved in regards to the call, because it allows us to go on in our project authentically. As Heidegger puts it, “When the call is understood with an existentiell kind of hearing, such understanding is more authentic the more non-relationally Dasein hears and understands its own Being-appealed-to, and the less the meaning the call gets perverted by what one says or by what is fitting and accepted [was sich gehört und gilt].” This quote reveals that in understanding, there is a reflection before answering the call, deeming answering the “call of conscience” as a responsive act.

In fact, understanding the call is rather a mode-of-being, a mode-of-being that is characterised by responsiveness. The reason why understanding is the equivalent of responding is because of the contemplative nature of understanding something requires us to reflect. As I have already explained, understanding and answering the call leads us to take up our existential project, Dasein and to be responsible for our being. This is a key point for Heidegger and responsiveness, because it is the response, where responsibility is born. Thus forth, responsibility is a result of the response.

In recognising that both the act of the “call of conscience” and the answering to the call are explainable through responsiveness demonstrates that Heidegger was for substantial part, an advocate for responsiveness as a philosophy. However I cannot claim that for the entire Heideggerian outlook is a responsive philosophy. Potentially the most important finding in this essay is in regards to answering the call and taking responsibility for ones existence, because not only is it one of the most overtly obvious results of responding, but it expresses potentially the most significant meaning or outcome for responsiveness, Heidegger and existing itself.


[1] M Heidegger, Being and Time (London, UK: SCM Press, 1962)

[3] Haim Gordon, Dictionary of Existentialism (United States of America, Greenwood Publishing Group, 1999), 133.

Like this:

LikeLoading...

Comments

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *